Market-based non-solutions

Though I've taken a pause to watch DVDs, I'm still studying economics.

I've said before how impressed I am with Economics Explained: Everything You Need to Know About How the Economy Works and Where It's Going by Robert Heilbroner and Lester Thurow. Having finished it I feel like I have enough of a grip on the basic concepts to understand a discussion because I know which words are terms of art; to actually think about stuff I need a bit more.

At any rate, this post was inspired by a comment made about markets clearing.

How many of you know what "markets clearing" means?

I thought so.

I've scanned and uploaded a chunk of a chapter explaining what "supply" and "demand" are in microeconomic terms, a nice, bland HTML file. No graphs or anything; you have to get the book for that. But just in case you don't like links and such:

On the other hand, the system has the defects of its virtues. If it is efficient and dynamic, it is also devoid of values. It recognizes no valid claim to the goods and services of society except those of wealth and income. Those with incomes and wealth are entitled to the goods and services that the economy produces; those without income and wealth receive nothing.

This blindness of the market to any claim on society's output except wealth or income creates very serious problems. It means that those who inherit large incomes are entitled to large shares of output, even though they may have produced nothing themselves. It means that individuals who have no wealth and who cannot produce-perhaps simply because they cannot find work-have no way of gaining an income through the economic mechanism. To abide just by the market system of distribution, we would have to be willing to tolerate individuals starving on the street.

Therefore, every market society interferes to some extent with the outcome of the price-rationing system. It does so when an "economic problem" crosses the line to become a "social problem."

And the extended text has enough of the chapter to let you know where this is coming from.THE MARKET AS A RATIONING SYSTEM

Now look at what this shows us. All the buyers and sellers who can afford and are willing to pay the equilibrium price (or more) will get the goods they want. All those who cannot, will not. So, too, all the sellers who are willing and able to supply the commodity at its equilibrium price or less will be able to consummate sales. All those who cannot will not.

Thus the market, in establishing an equilibrium price, has in effect allocated the goods to some buyers and withheld it from others. It has permitted some sellers to do business and denied that privilege to others. Note that the market is, in this way, a means of excluding certain people from economic activity, namely customers with too little money or with too weak desires, or suppliers unwilling or unable to operate at a certain price. It is, in fact, a rationing mechanism!

Our view of the price system as a rationing mechanism helps to clarify the meaning of two words we often hear as a result of intervention into the market-rationing process: shortage and surplus.

In everyday language we often say that there is a shortage of housing for low-income groups-meaning that poor people cannot find housing that they can afford. Yet as we have seen in every market there are always some buyers who are unsatisfied. We have previously noted, for instance, that in our market for blouses, all buyers who could not or would not pay $19.95 had to go without. Does this mean there was a shortage? In economic terminology, no. A shortage in economic terminology does not mean there are no unsatisfied people in a market. It means only that no one who is willing and able to meet the going price is unable to get the goods he or she wants.

In a market that "clears," no such buyers exist. To be sure, there may be many would-be buyers happy to buy blouses at, say, $16.95, but there are none for sale at that price. Thus "shortage" only refers to buyers who are willing and able to pay the going price but who cannot get their demands filled at that price.

Why not? The answer must be that some nonmarket agency-in medieval times, perhaps the Church; in our day, more likely some government agency-has set the price below the equilibrium level. Now buyers who could not get blouses at $16.95 come crowding into the store-only to find that there are not enough blouses to meet the swollen demand. Who will go without-the buyers who were willing and able to pay the higher price, or the new "lucky" buyers who are now able to pay the lower price? The answer is queues in stores to buy things before they are gone, under-the-counter deals to get on a preferred list, or black or gray markets selling goods illegally at higher prices than are officially sanctioned.

The opposite takes place with a surplus. Suppose the government sets a price floor above the equilibrium price, for instance, when it supports the price of corn above its free-market price. In this situation, the quantity supplied is greater than that demanded. In a free market, the price would fall until the two quantities were equal. But if the government continues to support the commodity, then the quantity bought by private industries does not have to be as large as the quantity offered by farmers. Unsold amounts-the surplus-will be bought by government.

Thus the words "shortage" and "surplus" mean situations in which sellers and buyers remain active and unsatisfied because the price mechanism has not eliminated them from the marketplace. This is very different from a free market where buyers and sellers who cannot meet the going price are not taken into account. Most people, who have no demand for fresh caviar at eighty dollars per tin, do not complain of a caviar shortage. If the price of fresh caviar were set by government decree at one dollar a pound, there would soon be a colossal shortage.

What about the situation with low-cost housing? Essentially what we mean when we talk of a shortage of inexpensive housing is that we view the outcome of this particular market situation with noneconomic eyes and pronounce the result distasteful. By the standards of the market, the poor who cannot afford to buy housing are only one more example of the rationing process that takes place in every market. When we single out certain goods or services (such as a doctor's care) as being in "short supply," we imply that we do not approve of the price mechanism as the appropriate means of allocating scarce resources in these particular instances. Our disapproval does not imply that the market is not as efficient a distributor as ever. What we do not like is the outcome of the market-rationing process. In other words, for all its worth, efficiency is not the only criterion by which we judge the market system.

That word efficiency brings us to the last and perhaps most important aspect of how markets work. This is the ability of markets to allocate goods and services more effectively than other systems of rationing, particularly planning in one form or another.

There is no question that the market is one of the most extraordinary social inventions in human history. If we recall the attributes of the pre-market societies of antiquity we may remember that they typically suffered from two difficulties. If they were run mainly by tradition, they tended to be inert, passive, changeless. It's very hard to get things done in a traditional economy if anything has to be done in a new way-if, for instance, a change in climate forces a search for new ways of growing food or catching game.

A command system, ancient or modern, has a different inherent problem. It is good in undertaking big projects but not in running a complex system. In addition, the presence of political power in the economic mechanism, either as a large bureaucracy or as an authority capable of sticking its nose into daily life, becomes an endless source of inefficiency and irritation.

Against these two difficulties, the price system has two great advantages: it is highly dynamic, and it is self-enforcing. That is, on the one hand it provides an easy avenue for change to enter the system, as imaginative or ambitious individuals try new approaches or invent new goods. In addition, it allows these individuals to get a fair trial without first getting anyone's official permission: all you have to do is to sell your product!

The second (self-enforcing) attribute of the market is especially useful with regard to the rationing function. In place of ration tickets, with their almost inevitable black markets or cumbersome inspectorates or queues of customers trying to be first in line, the price system operates without any kind of visible administrative apparatus or side effects. The energies that must go into planning, or the frictions that come out of it, are alike rendered unnecessary by this remarkable self-policing mechanism. With all its difficulties, which we have by no means fully enumerated or examined, it is this capacity for self-adjustment and self-correction that sets economics apart from-although by no means above-its sister social disciplines.

That always comes as a surprise. We think of rationing as a formal, inflexible way of sharing goods-one ticket, one loaf of bread. This seems just the opposite of the free, unimpeded flux of marketplace. And in some ways it is indeed as different as can be. Just the same, the price mechanism performs a rationing function, exactly as do ration tickets. Money can be thought of as a system of flexible ration coupons. Indeed, there is nothing more important to grasp than this central purpose that markets serve. They are simply sophisticated rationing mechanisms.

On the other hand, the system has the defects of its virtues. If it is efficient and dynamic, it is also devoid of values. It recognizes no valid claim to the goods and services of society except those of wealth and income. Those with incomes and wealth are entitled to the goods and services that the economy produces; those without income and wealth receive nothing.

This blindness of the market to any claim on society's output except wealth or income creates very serious problems. It means that those who inherit large incomes are entitled to large shares of output, even though they may have produced nothing themselves. It means that individuals who have no wealth and who cannot produce-perhaps simply because they cannot find work-have no way of gaining an income through the economic mechanism. To abide just by the market system of distribution, we would have to be willing to tolerate individuals starving on the street.

Therefore, every market society interferes to some extent with the outcome of the price-rationing system. It does so when an "economic problem" crosses the line to become a "social problem." In times of military emergency the nation issues special permits that take precedence over money and thereby prevents the richer members of society from buying up all the supplies of scarce and costly items. In depressed areas, it may distribute basic food or clothing to those who have no money to buy them. Historically speaking, it has used taxes and transfers to an ever-increasing extent to replace the ration tickets of money in accordance with the prevailing sense of justice, rather than by the standards of efficiency. It is, in fact, in the tension between the claims of efficiency and those of justice that much of the division between conservative and liberal points of view is to be found

Posted by Prometheus 6 on January 7, 2004 - 9:59am :: Economics
 
 

Comment viewing options

Select your preferred way to display the comments and click "Save settings" to activate your changes.

I'm disappointed that the effects of charity (which is what his "inheritance problem" actually is) is completely ignored, at least in the context of this section. The church example isn't a changing of the market price -- it is the giving away of the difference.

Posted by  Phelps (not verified) on January 7, 2004 - 12:27pm.

BTW, I don't know if you mentioned it earlier, but I just finished Eat the Rich. I enjoyed it.

Posted by  Phelps (not verified) on January 7, 2004 - 12:29pm.

That wasn't on my list, which is WAY too long as it is. As things stand, the next serious book (to be read immediately after "A Heartbreaking Work of Staggering Genius") is The Mystery of Capital.

Posted by  P6 (not verified) on January 7, 2004 - 1:31pm.

Yeah, but Eat the Rich isn't a serious book. It's P.J. O'Rourke. You know, the thinking man's Dave Barry. It's only about economics because economics is so hilarous.

Posted by  Phelps (not verified) on January 7, 2004 - 2:07pm.

Heilbronner did a nice job on his _Worldly Philospophers_ text to quickly summarize the main concepts of the classical economists. Thurow's _Head to Head_ however shows the extent to which his biases for state directed economic solutions affected his analytical skill when discussing political economy

Posted by  mark safranski (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 5:10am.

"It means that those who inherit large incomes are entitled to large shares of output, even though they may have produced nothing themselves. It means that individuals who have no wealth and who cannot produce-perhaps simply because they cannot find work-have no way of gaining an income through the economic mechanism. To abide just by the market system of distribution, we would have to be willing to tolerate individuals starving on the street."The problem with this paragraph is twofold. One it implies a static state economy which is false - generally worthless heirs fritter away vast fortunes within a generation and generally most people rise in socioeconomic status and wealth throughout their lives. Secondly, this statement holds true only on the extremes - starvation was not the historical rule anywhere - even in communist countries which are highly prone to famines- because if it was, society would have collapsed. It is even less frequent in capitalist nations than in those with traditional or command economies. To take the above paragraph as a justification for using a non-market economy as the general organizing principle is akin to banning private ownership of cars because there might be auto accidents. If it's used as a qualifier for the need to remediate the extreme margin of market activity costs it's more sensible.

Posted by  mark safranski (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 5:37am.

To take the above paragraph as a justification for using a non-market economy as the general organizing principle is akin to banning private ownership of cars because there might be auto accidents. If it's used as a qualifier for the need to remediate the extreme margin of market activity costs it's more sensible.

The authors are definite about the advantages of the market system but just as definite about its limits.I am an unrepentant capitalist. I'm also unrepentant about my concern for the general human condition in this society and culture, as well as the world-wide society and culture our dominance creates, and about my disdain for political Platonism single concept solutions to multi-dimensional problems. The FACT is that market solutions are not even applicaple to many of the problems we have to solve. The FACT is many of our problems ARE the very '"economic problem" [crossing] the line to become a "social problem"' referred to in the last excerpted paragraph.And the FACT is, this comment is becoming a whole post. :->

Posted by  P6 (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 6:39am.

I'm a Free-Marketeer Prom but a rational one - there's always a category of public goods that the market by it's nature will not deliver or deliver well. I recognize that in a democratic society there will be some political limitations to the free market that would be unwise and counterproductive to try and cross in order to achieve theoretical purity. Overall though, these caveats should remain caveats. State intervention as a model instead of as an exception not only produces less impressive economic results than a free market - even when well-intentioned- it's actions when negative are far less likely to be self-correcting.

Posted by  mark safranski (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 10:49am.

I don't want state intervention in the market, but I don't want market intervention in the state either. I see the confusion over whether the market is a function of society or the other way around to be a major problem. I mean, what's the primary need here?To me, the ideal would be nationalizing all necessities…and I'm not trying to hear anyone say they need a cashmire coat and alligator shoes, you know? I think the market can function outside the realm of that which is minimally required to get by…since folks seem to feel the market is so agile and adaptive while the government is so stodgy and glacial, it only makes sense that the adjustments be in the function more capable of adjusting.Of course there'd be mad discussion about exactly WHAT is a necessity (for instance, I'd say a reflexive upgrade of electric generation and transmission facilities would be a necessity). Such discussions will keep all the politicians and pundits gainfully employed. But a general admission that there are things which can not be market driven, things that should not be market driven and things that, because of our values, we simply do not want to be market driven, is a start. And frankly, we don't have that start.

Posted by  P6 (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 1:56pm.

As you might expect I'm not a big fan of nationalization but utilities lend themselves well to that precisely because they are so capital intensive as to be within a stone's throw of public goods like the interstate highway system or Fermilab or NASA. It's difficult for any private investor to enter the market because cost presents such a high barrier to entry. Left to the market alone these fields usually become natural monopolies, duopolies and oligopolies because that is the only level of competition that can return a profit on such long term capital investments.Other necessities do not though, food being a prime example where nationalization policies have the worst possible effects. India and China did not feed themselves or become food exporters until the most onerous socialist regs were lifted. The Soviets did not match the 1913 harvest, when most Russian peasants were incredibly backward smallholders and tenant farmers, until the 1960's. I would also argue that nationalized health care systems are least effective at delivering high quality care and that some of their lowered costs in dollar terms are a result simply of rationing care. People wait for non-emergency surgery and live with pain or illness ( or die waiting )in the meantime. There is also the hidden cost of the brightest demographic of people gravitating to other, less controlled, more renumerative fields, instead of medicine.

Posted by  mark safranski (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 6:37pm.

So nationalize a chunk of the food industry. More accurately, have a nationalized means of providing everyone with all the peanut butter, grits and iceburg lettuce the can eat. The most boring subsistance imaginable (I'd suggest the development of those yeast varieties the science fiction books keep going on about, but everything we eat is processed corn already).As for health care, I refer you to a previous post because the comments strip out table tags.

Posted by  P6 (not verified) on January 8, 2004 - 8:19pm.